While I was rummaging through the science and philosophy magazines literally hanging off the sides of the bookshelves in my bedroom/office, I found this old gem of article from an Italian popular science magazine called “Le Scienze” (The Sciences) which is actually nothing more than the Italian version of Scientific American, containing mostly translations of SciAm articles from the English, but with the occasional outstanding contribution from some of the top matematicians and scientists working here in Italy.
In this particular case, the writer, Piergiorgio Odifreddi, is one of the top mathematical logicans in Italy. But he is also one of those great popularizers of science, ala Steven Jay Gould, Oliver Sacks and Steven Pincker, who know how to make complex ideas accesible to a popular audience without compromising the substance.
The title of the article is, “The Paradox of Democracy” and I think it should definitely interest even the non mathematically-inclined folks out there.
my translation from the Italian
Let’s begin with the problem of electoral districts. Since it never occurs in real life, as it does in Borge’s short story “the Parlaiment”, that every voter gets elected to office, the number of voters is always greater than the number of seats being contested, and the ratio bewteen the two is rarely an integral number.
In order to be fair, the distribution of seats should above all satisfy a principle of proportionality :
the number of seats assigned to a district on the basis of the size of the population, or to a party on the basis of the number of votes, should be one of the two approximations of that ratio. For example, if the seats to be assigned are ten, a party that wins 1/3 of the vote should receive three or four.A second obvious condition that should be satsified is monotonicity : if a party wins more votes than another, it shouldn’t receive less seats. And this should apply not only synchronically, in single elections, but diacronically, in different elections, with respect to the ratio between the percentages of votes.
But in 1982 two US mathematicians, Michael Balinsky and Peyton Young, proved a surpising theorem: there is no general method for distributing seats in a manner that will satisfy the two aforementioned conditions at the same time. As soon as there are, in fact, at least four parties or districts, and seven seats being contested, there exist distributions of votes that make the thing impossible.
For example, let’s suppose that in a first election the four parties A,B,C and D obtain, respectively, the following distributions of votes relative to the seven seats: 5.01 – 0.67 – 0.67 – 0.65. And that, in a second election, the distributions become: 3.99 – 2.00 – 0.50 – 0.51. Synchronic proportionality and monotonicity would require that in the first election the distribution of seats be: five to A, one each to B and C, and none to D. In the second: four to A, two to B, none to C, and one to D. But in that way diachronic monotonicity is violated, because A loses a seat and D gains one, even though A increased his number of votes with respect to D from 7.5 to almost 8 times.
Naturally, the principle of proportionality is rejected by the majority based electoral systems, which however have their own nice little problems. For example, it’s possible that a party with slightly less than 50% of the national vote not obtain a single seat, and that every seat goes instead to parties with a minumum national representation. It’s sufficient in fact that in each district one and the same national party obtain 50% – 1 of the votes, and that a small local party obtain 50% + 1, in order for the seat to go to the latter.
Another problem of majoritarian systems is that they require an aggregation of policital forces in two counterpoised blocks. The deleterious consequences become evident immediatly by comparing the electoral campaigns of the two parties to the selling of icecream on a linear beach about a chilomter long: the optimal disposition of the two icecrem vendors is 250 from the etxremes, becasuse in this way no bather has to travel more than 250 meters to buy an icecream. But if one of the vendors moves slightly toward the center, he won’t lose the the buyers at the extreme and he will take some from his competitor: since the phenomenon works symmetrically, the reciprocal movements of the vendors toward the center will leave them both at the center, leaving everyone else underserved and those in the center spoiled.
Now isn’t that one of the best illustrations you’ve ever read of the fundamental problem with majoritarianism? Brilliant!!!
The rest of the article discusses Kenneth Arrow’s impossibility theorem and illustrates why democracy, when carefully and precisely defined, is mathematically impossible!!
Arrow’s theorem of 1951 demonstrates in fact that there do not exist systems which satify the minimal conditions which are normally required for democracy: the fact, that is, that each voter has the right to freely choose the candidate he wants (freedom of choice); that if all voters prefer one candidate over another, the latter must never be elected (unanimity); and that the choice of the winner depend only on the votes expressed and not on other factors (indepdence from irrelevant alternative).
In reality, things are even worse than they seem. A theorem of Amartya Sen from 1970 poves in fact that the first two conditions are already incompatible wiht the possibility that , in one society, more than one person can have rights. This is evident in the case of rights regarding the same alternative: if in fact two individuals each have a right regarding the choice between A and B, it is sufficne that one choose A and the other B in order to obtain a contradiction.
From Sen’s theorem it is easy to derive Arrow’s. Lets’ consider two alterantives A and B not indifferent to society. If noone had rights on them, evey individual could prefer to choose the alternative contrary to that of the whole society, by the freedom of choice. But if everyone beahved in the same manner, the independnce from irrelevnat alteranatives and unanimity would contrain society to choose the alternative whch everyone prefers, contary to the hypothesis that that choice is in fact the other.
Therfore, for every alternative not indifferent for society, there must exist an individual who has a right WRT it. By Sen’s theorem, this individual must always be the same, becaseu at the most only one person can have rights. But one persaon who has rights overall the altrenatives is a dictator…….
I’ll leave you all to tease this one out for a while.
Yitsa tima toa sleepa. i’ll try to respond to any coments tomorrow.
More hopeful than Plato – a dictator could be benevolent(?). But then, if you’re democratically elected, and benevolent, there’s a better chance you’d maintain the system. And it reminds me of what W likes to refer to himself as.
Actaully, mny people on dkos completely misunderstood this. SURPRISE!!! They thouhght i was seriously sustaining that the author, and/or I, was seriously sustaining the thesis that democracy is impossible. I only used that headling to capture attention (that’s what they do in the MSM, right?) and generate discussion.
The actual title of the article is “The pardoxes of Democracy!!” and here’s how Odifreddi actually concludes, in case anybody still doesn’t get it: “Those who maintain that dictatorship is incompatible with democracy, still has to deal wit other problems: mathetamatics demonstartes that the entire process of voting, from the establishment of districts to the electoral mechanism for the choice of a winner, cannot be organized in an optimal manner.
But, contenting oneself with less than the optimal, one can anyhow find good organizations, and certainly bettrer than the aweful ones implemeted by leaders of the past, or proposed by those of the future.
Odifreddi publishes monthly columns on the mathematical aspects of whatever’s in the recent science news: biology, politoligy, economics, physics or just aspects of everyday life. And he’s quote good at it.
His intention is to make people think about these aspects and to educate them about math.
So please lightenn up, some of you folks out there.
It does capture attention, and you don’t give the impression of advocating this – as a matter of fact your diary is ambiguous on the matter. With my comment I did try to figure out where you stand, but alas, it was not meant to be – I am as ignorant as before. LOL
So let me start – hopefully slightly ambiguous, but less than yourself – just remember accusation is not fact. My husband is constantly accusing me of being Platonic in my views of democracy, because I do feel democracy has little to safeguard itself from electing tyranny, and I do believe you can use democracy to create a non-democracy. Democracy is full of paradoxes, but I think it can be structured to be less so.
My position on electoral systems can’t be any better or more clearly expressed than what I wrote above. So I’ll have to repeat myself here:
It cannot be organized in an optimal manner.
But, contenting oneself with less than the optimal, one can anyhow find good organizations, and certainly bettrer than the aweful ones implemeted by leaders of the past, or proposed by those of the future.
As to specific proposals for a better system, I provide a sort of sketch of one below in my reply to soj.
Marie-Jean-Antoine-Nicolas de Caritat, Marquis de Condorcet.
His most important work was on probability and the philosophy of mathematics. His most important treatise was Essay on the Application of Analysis to the Probability of Majority Decisions (1785), an extremely important work in the development of the theory of probability.
He is known for the Condorcet Paradox which points out that it is possible that a majority prefers option A over option B, a majority prefers option B over option C, and yet a majority prefers option C over option A. (Thus, “majority prefers” is not transitive.)
Yes, I’m familar with the paradox of transitivity of Condorcet.
It’s another fine example of the mathematical limitations of electoral systems.
Good point!!
Thanks for the Diary and translation gilgamesh…
Reminds me of a woman whose name I forget (I believe her initials are LG) this early in the AM, she’s of Indian origin, and her analyses of how congressional districting in the U.S. defeat the effectiveness of 1 person 1 vote. However she had a brilliant theory (several actually) which was what I remember as the “multiple vote”.
Let’s imagine voter X has 5 votes, not 1. X can give all five votes to a single candidate or perhaps 4 to one candidate and 1 to another, etc. This counterbalances the tendency that the two big parties getting votes simply because others would be a “waste” since third parties are not as “electable”.
She also had some good electoral theories about instant runoff and more which I forget at this hour. It’s amazing how a little mathematics can help clear up some of the most basic elements of democracy.
Pax
Thats sounds very similar to the graduated sytem based on order of preference that the two US authors propose in the adjoining artcile about improving elctoral systems.
The idea is simple: every voter gets to rank their preference of candidates from 1 to 4, say, if their are four candidates. Each voter, that is, assigns 4 points to their most prefered candiate, 3 points to their second choice, 3 to their third and so on. The winner under this system is whoever totals the most points. However, it too has problems!!
Immagine that candidate A receives 49 million (49%) out 100 million votes. Candidated B recieves 48 million (48%). Candidate C receives 2 million (2%) and candiate D receives one miliion (1%).
As a result candidate A will receive 49* 4= 196 million points from the voters who prefer her. The voters of C have chosen A as their second candidate. Therefore A recieves 6 million votes from this source. Voters of B and D have chosen A for third place. Therefore she receives 48*2=96 million + 2 million = 98 million points. The total is 300 million.
Applying the same calclaution to B, she receives 48*4=192 million from those who rank her first. Voters of A, by hypothesis, have chosen B as their second best candidate. Therefore B receives 49*3=147 million points from these voters. Voters of D have chosen B as their second choice, therefore she recives 1 million votes, etc…The total is 346 million points for B.
B wins in spite of the fact that A received a higher percentage of the votes. But what happens if the order of prefernce is slighlty changed so that B voters choose B, A, D and C in that order. Now A would obtain
348 points: 196 milloon from A voters, 48*3=144 points from B voters, etc.. while B would remain at 346 million points. A would win but her victory would depend on a violation of the principle of independence from irrelevant alternatives(third candiates).
However, this can be repaired by introducing the rule of the true majority. Accoring to this rule, A is prefered by the voters of A and of C over B and thereby recives 51% of the vote in both of the above cases. You now have independence from irrelevant alternative
A British logican wrote a paper in … 1924?… dealing with variables sharing a common property. This is a problem in combinatorial computing and a subject of ongoing research for those who care about such things.
I’m only very superficially aware of Ramsey numbers and the field it spawned but – if I’m not off in the weeds – it is known there are discontinuous discrete values that can be applied to the formula:
P(x,y) ; where
P is the property; x and y represent the arithmetic quantification satisfying the distribution of P. It turns out these values are discontinuous in respect to some P‘s. I do not know if they are also necessarily (Always) non-linear but when there is escape bifurcation chaos needs to be suspected. (But then I’m slightly ‘hipped’ on Chaos.)
Thinking about it, a little more, this could also be a problem that falls in the set of Weierstrass equations – continuous but non-differentiable. (?) Planck resolved the difficulty, at least in the first order derivative, by inventing quantum mechanics but I know even less about QM than I do Ramsey Numbers.
What I’m trying to get at here is to question Statistical Analysis, with a concurrent use of permutation and probability, being the right tool for the job.
and I also wish people would stop posting interesting diaries so I can get some freaking work done!
You will excuse me for not being able to answer your own
combinatorial difficulties, but it’s been centuries since I last opened my undergraduarte textbooks for my BS
in Comp. Sci, and I’m not particularly motivated to do it right now.
My advise to you is that you sens this problem immediatly to Glenn Reynolds over at Instapundit or to someone at Powerline. After all, these are the leading award-winning bloggers of our time. They should know somehting, right????