As disenchantment with Tony Blair boosted the Liberal Democrats, Labour has been playing a familiar card for all it’s worth: “Join ranks against the Tory menace!” But should the LibDem supporters pay heed or seal their ears to the sirens of strategic voting?
Here is Blair’s heir apparent, Gordon Brown, pleading in The Guardian:
But there is no advance for the progressive cause if a Labour vote switches to Liberal Democrat in a Labour-held seat where the Conservatives are second, and so allows the Conservatives in by the back door.
Needless to say, the background is the UK’s First-Past-the-Post System (FPPS), which gives a marked incentive to vote strategically in order to avoid the notorious spoiler effect. Specifically, it invites a compromising strategy, whereby one votes for an alternative other than one’s true preference because it has better chances. But is that ploy as good as its reputation?
In a superb little article from last year, Empty Moat hits the pig on the snout:
Approaching the problem from a Rational Choice-theoretical point of view, he defines the net expected utility for a voter as the sum of three factors: the Immediate-Election Utility, the Policy-Shift Utility, and the Future-Election Utility. Let us adopt his terminology while expanding his analysis a bit.
Immediate-Election Utility
Empty Moat defines this as follows:
From this flows the rationale of the compromising strategy, as articulated by Anthony Downs in a classic treatise:
An Economic Theory of Democracy (48). Addison Wesley: Boston 1957.
Now, many people under FPPS do indeed worry that their vote, if not cast for the winner, is a ‘wasted’ one. But consider: How is it any more wasted than the spurious votes for the winner, of which there are typically thousands? Clearly, in terms of Immediate-Election Utility, any vote is wasted that fails to affect the outcome. The common illusion to the contrary is perhaps due to the satisfaction of ‘belonging to the winning team.’ In fact, it could be that many vote for the expected winner partly to associate themselves with the winner – an hypothesis it might be interesting to test.
Undeniably, the Immediate-Election Utility of compromising often exceeds that of voting sincerely. But so what? The Immediate-Election Utility is anyhow negligible, as even in a small constituency the likelihood of any given vote being decisive approaches nil. Indeed, the so-called Paradox of Voting inspired by Downs’ above cited work drives this home: Why does anyone bother voting at all? After all, the expected utility of doing something else with one’s time should dwarf any hope of swaying the election. So if queing up makes sense, it presumably is not because of Immediate-Election Utility. (Some game-theoretical models question this but are indeterminate.)
Why, then, might it be rational to vote from an instrumentally rational perspective? If we broaden the focus to include longer-term utility considerations, the mystery largely dissolves; but so does the case for a compromising voting strategy.
Policy-Shift Utility
One reason to vote is to convey one’s will to the parties to impact their nominations. Empty Moat sums it up impeccably:
Furthermore, in cases where the Immediate-Election Utility of a compromise vote is highest (close races), the Policy-Shift Utility of a true-preference vote is also high. Parties in close competetion have more need to capture votes, so a true-preference vote would have more policy-shifting utility.
By supporting the compromise party over their first choice, voters positively encourage it to ignore their concerns while petitioning them, Gordon Brown-style, to always circle the wagons ‘one more time.’ In that sense their votes are worse than wasted.
Future-Election Utility
Then there is party-building. Empty Moat:
- It will increase recognition of the party (this yields diminishing returns for larger parties, until it becomes negligible), which will help some voters discover the party as their true preference.
- It will increase the respectability of the party. Voters with limited information on the various policies and related consequences of their choices will draw some information from the expressed preferences of others.
- It will increase the recognized viability of the party. The expected utility of voting for the party will increase for other voters.
When you cast a compromising vote, all those benefits transfer from the party you prefer to its rival.
We can add a fourth effect: You help perpetuate the very system that under-represents your position. For just as, in accordance with the principle known as Duverger’s Law, FPPS promotes a two-party system, the latter also favors FPPS. In the UK, neither Tories nor Labour has the slightest interest in a more proportional arrangement. Hence a vote for one of them is a vote for the status quo, where a large body of opinion is unrepresented in the halls of power.
Non-utilitarian factors
Besides the longer-term utilitarian considerations we have looked at, there are possible non-utilitarian, though not thereby irrational, reasons for voting. These ascribe intrinsic value to voting and in so doing, strengthen the case for voting sincerely.
For instance, voting might be seen as a civic duty, a natural interpretation of which is to select the best available candidate as one sees it. Voting can also be viewed as a manifestation of fellowship with kindred spirits, or even as a kind of existential choice that helps express and fix one’s identity. But that requires for people to vote their conscience.
So why not vote Nader, then?
An objection may occur to some. It may seem that the argument set forth above, to anyone favoring Nader’s platform over Kerry’s, would justify voting Nader in the recent US election. And reasonably or not, that might be seen as plainly a reductio ad absurdum of said argument. But a reply is at hand: Nader, by running as a likely spoiler against the only realistic challenger to an incumbent so diametrically opposed to his platform, arguably proved himself unfit for public office. Unlike any given vote, his choice might have altered the outcome, and it thus reflects poorly on his judgment, or character, or both – giving everyone a reason to avoid him.
Now, one could make a similar charge against LibDem candidates in constituencies like those described by Brown. Disanalogies abound, however. Unlike voting LibDem, voting Nader would have little Future-Election Utility, since he wasn’t building a party. And while it might have a certain Policy-Shift Utility, a vote for the comparatively less peripheral LibDems would surely have much more. Finally, many progressives would think a Bush reelection far more dangerous than a Tory in 10 Downing Street.
To conclude then: Let us hope the Brits have left strategy to generals and chess players, and voted with their hearts.
– whose fine diary entry yesterday prompted this one.
for another excellent diary — not that you write any other kind =)
Well I walked down to Ashton today and cast my vote for the LibDems. It felt a little weird not to be voting Labour (I grew up in a family in which voting Labour — albeit in New Zealand — was pretty much an article of faith until the advent of MMP). But the Ashton MP voted for war and for the curtailment of civil liberties along with various other nasty bits and bobs, which to my mind precluded voting for him.
Had he been one of the rebel MPs that voted against war, I most likely would have voted Labour: MPs prepared to vote their conscience and defy Blair are precisely what the Labour Party needs right now.
I wouldn’t say that my vote was just a protest vote though. Even though I hope that the Labour Party will reform itself sufficiently that I can vote Labour in future elections, I would like to see a stronger LibDem party — whether as a coalition partner in government or as the main party in opposition.
For putting a human face (or font, I guess) on the choices facing the UK voters, and for the ways you can vote as your conscience dictates, without the entire house of cards falling down.
And thanks, Sirocco, for also putting the Nader thing in perspective. That is such a great way to explain it.
Funny to think that the UK is more democratic than the US, but less so than other democracies.
Have we had a diary yet examining various democracies and what factors makes them more democratic than the next?
I’m planning on writing one on MMP as used in N.Z. sometime in the next couple of days.
It will give me an excuse to look at how they managed to get it in (despite neither of the major parties being fans of it).
Oh cool, I’ll look forward to reading it. It’s sometimes difficult to grasp the parliamentary elections and how those all work, where it seems that even if you win you can lose, and even if you lose you are likely a winner of some sort.
Oh dear, will I have to contribute something on the single transferable vote (or preferential) system used in Australia?
Yep. =)
Glad you landed on the right side, Dove! Proud of you… 😉
.
Follow the definite results as they come in at BBC — ELECTION 2005
Tony Blair is on course to win an historic third term for Labour but with a reduced majority, according to a joint BBC/ITV exit poll. The poll suggests Mr Blair’s majority will be reduced from 160 to 66.
The findings – based on 19,800 voters at 120 polling stations across the UK – were announced as polls closed in the 2005 general election.
The BBC’s exit poll suggests Labour’s concern during the campaign, that it might perform less well in marginal seats it is defending could be realised.
The exit poll suggests that on average, the party’s vote has fallen by just over 6 points in seats it is defending against a Conservative challenge, compared with a 5 point drop across the country as a whole.
BBC Political Editor Andrew Marr said: “If it is anything like that, it is a lot worse for the Labour Party than most people have assumed.”
Oui – Liberté – Egalité – Fraternité
Well put – with Nader there certainly would be no chance of any sort of coalition, the type of democracy in the US is so different you cannot always vote with your heart.
.
Just on BBC News —
The Conservative Party Leader has stepped down.
Oui – Liberté – Egalité – Fraternité
Thanks, Sirocco – the three Rational Choice categories are very thought-provoking.
I’ve usually known what you are calling ‘strategic voting’ as ‘tactical voting’, and the discussions I’ve heard/seen about tactical voting have focussed on the Immediate-Election Utility of the vote. Now that I think about Policy-Shift Utility and Future-Election Utility, I realise that a succesful tactical vote may not be a very strategic vote!
I think that Duverger’s law (that FPPS promotes a two-party system) deserves a bit of scrutiny. In the context you have used it here, and in the Electowiki definition you linked to, ‘FPPS’ means plurality voting in single-member electorates. In contrast, I’ve always understood first-past-the-post to refer solely to the voting system. Plurality voting can be applied to elections for more than one position – an example is the election of corporate directors under Australia’s Corporations Law.
My view is that it is the single-member electorates, rather than the plurality voting mechanism, which seem to produce two-party systems. As the Wiki notes, we have single transferable votes in Australian elections (a description of how this works for single member electorates is here), and also what is effectively a two-party system. Surprisingly, when I looked at what is usually considered the extreme case of multi-party systems, Italy (2001 results here and here), I found that there are essentially only two parties elected from single-member electorates. The other parties gain their seats through the proportional representation component of the electoral system.
Thanks for your thoughtful comment!
I’m also used to called it ‘tactical voting,’ but used ‘strategic’ here since that seems the more common term.
Speaking of FPPS instead of ‘plurality voting in single-member electorates,’ as we always called it in Political Science class, was another and perhaps more unfortunate concession to popular usage. On reflection I agree that the more technical term would have been better.
It’s an intriguing idea that the single-member electorates, not the plurality mechanism, spawns two-party systems. The Australia and Italy examples are thought-provoking. A possible counter-example might be US Senate races, which have plurality voting in two-member electorates yet invariably elect either a Democrat or a Republican despite a growing number of third-party or independent challengers. Then again, this might be due to the difficulty of taking on those extremely well-established parties.
I’ll have to mull your idea over more. Meanwhile it would be well worth a diary entry of its own, if you are so inclined.
Although there are two US Senators per State, I think that this is actually another example of single-member electorates, because only one is elected at a time. To quote Wikipedia:
Good point. You may be onto something then.